Editorial
The ethics of infant male circumcision
Brian D Earp
INTRODUCTION
Is the non-therapeutic circumcision of
infant males morally permissible? The most
recent major development in this longsimmering debate was the 2012 release of a
policy statement and technical report on
circumcision by the American Academy of
Pediatrics (AAP). In these documents, the
US paediatricians’ organisation claimed that
the potential health benefits of infant circumcision now outweigh the risks and
costs. They went on to suggest that their
analysis could be taken to justify the decision of parents to choose circumcision for
their incompetent children.1
Circumcision and ‘health benefits’
The AAP’s pronouncement unleashed a firestorm of commentary, much of it censorious. In this issue, human rights attorney J
Steven Svoboda and Professor of Clinical
Paediatrics Robert Van Howe take the AAP
to taski for committing numerous significant
errors, both in their analysis of relevant
evidence and in basic medical-ethical reasoning.3 In addition, an independent international panel—composed of 38 leading
paediatricians, paediatric surgeons, urologists, medical ethicists and heads of hospital
boards and children’s health societies—has
likewise condemned the findings of the AAP.
Writing in the journal Pediatrics, these
authors state:
Only one of the arguments put forward
by the American Academy of Pediatrics
has some theoretical relevance in relation
to infant male circumcision; namely, the
possible protection against urinary tract
infections in infant boys, which can easily
be treated with antibiotics without tissue
loss. The other claimed health benefits,
including protection against HIV/AIDS,
genital herpes, genital warts, and penile
cancer, are questionable, weak, and likely
to have little public health relevance in a
Western context, and they do not represent compelling reasons for surgery
before boys are old enough to decide for
themselves.4
i
A formal response by the AAP has been
published alongside the critique by Svoboda
and Van Howe.2
Correspondence to Oxford Uehiro Centre for
Practical Ethics, Suite 8, Littlegate House, St Ebbes
Street, Oxford OX1 1PT, UK; brian.earp@gmail.com
Earp BD. J Med Ethics Month 2013 Vol 00 No 00
My own analysis of the AAP documents
—and of ‘health benefits’ defences of
circumcision generally—can be found
elsewhere.5 Let me turn my attention in
this editorial, then, to the question of cultural and religious justifications for the
procedure. These are more principally the
theme of the Special Issue, and have taken
centre stage especially in Europe since the
recent decision of a Cologne court that
ritual removal of the foreskin constitutes
an unconstitutional form of bodily injury.ii
day ritual circumcision not only inherits
and reflects, but also serves to perpetuate,
at least some of the underlying metaphysic of that earlier epoch.12
The result is a rather uncomfortable
tension between the implicit meta-ethical
logic of this prehistoric practice and the
normative foundation of (much of ) contemporary Western law and custom. As I
noted recently in The Philosophers’
Magazine:
Ritual circumcision is a pre-Enlightenment
tribal tradition. [Both the Jewish and
Islamic versions require] males [to sacrifice]
functional erogenous tissue to an excruciating surgery done years before they are old
enough to give [meaningful] consent. …
Both versions are consistent with the
norms of [patriarchy]; both elevate the
concerns of the community over the
freedom of the individual to make decisions about his own body in his own time;
and both brand a child with a permanent
mark of religious belonging despite the significant possibility that he may one day fail
to embrace the belief system and/or cultural practices of his parents.13
Circumcision as a religious practice
Defenders of religiously or culturally motivated circumcision sometimes stress that it
is an ancient tradition, stretching back thousands of years. By doing so they seem to
suggest that the sheer antiquity of the practice implies a kind of venerability, or even
sanctitude. How could the fundamental
legal status of so timeworn a religious
custom be seriously called into question?
This perspective is not uncommon, and
those who hold to it are undoubtedly
sincere in their convictions. In the United
States, especially, attitudes toward circumcision are predominantly favorable: there
—unlike in Europe, Canada, Australia and
New Zealand—circumcision remains a
popular, if waning, cultural habit even
outside of any religious context. Since
most
Americans,
including
many
American doctors, are simply unaware of
the complex anatomy and diverse sexual
functions of the foreskin (i.e., functions
that are necessarily lost to circumcision3)
the age-old benignity of ‘snipping it off ’
seems practically self-evident.
What is left unacknowledged by appeals
to antiquity, however, is that while they
can in some cases lend an air of historical
augustness, they can also signal the potential for the existence of an ethical minefield. In the case of circumcision, the
practice is so ancient that its origins can
be traced to a period as problematic as the
Bronze Age9—an era in which, as Hanoch
Ben Yami intimates,10 superstition reigned
supreme, harmful propitiations were the
norm, and women and children were considered chattel.iii Unfortunately, modern
ii
The Cologne court ruling is discussed in detail
by Reinhard Merkel and Holme Putzke,6 as
well as by Joseph Mazor7 and Matthew
Johnson.8
iii
See related arguments by Van Howe.11
By contrast, contemporary medical ethics
as well as the philosophical basis of many
modern legal codes came to fruition in a
seculariv, post-Enlightenment era—one that
favours a very different set of values from
the ones alluded to above.v These include
such concepts as autonomy, consent, individual rights, bodily integrity, the freedom to
join (or to leave) a religion, the needfulness
of protecting the vulnerable in society
against the unwarranted exertions of the
powerful, and a child’s interests in—or as
some would have it, ‘rights to’—selfdetermination and an open future.vi As
several of the contributors to this Special
Issue have taken pains to note, this deeplyrooted tension between pre- and postEnlightenment world views is the source of
much of the current—as well as historical—
controversy surrounding the ethics of infant
male circumcision.vii
Pre- vs. post-Enlightenment: resolving
the tension
How might this tension be resolved? Given
that Western societies have gradually succeeded in abandoning a very wide range of
once hallowed traditions that came to conflict with subsequent developments in law
and morality, one possible argument—and
iv
Or at least: non-ecclesiocratic.
See Svoboda.14
vi
For an in-depth discussion of the child’s right
to an open future, see Darby.15
vii
See also Earp and Darby.16
v
1
Editorial
one that is increasingly being advanced by
legal scholars, ethicists, and more liberalminded Muslims and Jews— is that the time
has come to likewise abandon the practice
of cutting off infants’ foreskins. If this were
accomplished through the enforcement of
existing prohibitions on committing acts of
sexual violence, it would certainly serve to
eliminate a number of clumsy inconsistencies in Western legal statutes. For example,
laws that uniquely exempt non-therapeutic
infant male circumcision from the application of (otherwise straightforwardly interpretable) definitions of criminal assault
could be relieved of their asterisks.viii
Pursuing an outright ban, however,
would seem to be rather extreme, heavyhanded or simply far-fetched. Indeed, an
immediate prohibition on religious circumcision would be premature (to say the
least), and likely even counterproductive.
Much more debate is needed, in both the
academic and the public arenas. At the
same time, however, one should remember
that it is already illegal in most jurisdictionsix to cut into the genitals of any female
human being, to any degree, with any
instrument, for any reason, at any age,
without her informed consent—and in
some places even with it—barring some
emergency related to health. Even the
tiniest ritual ‘nick’ is federally banned in the
USA, and this is an intervention that
removes no tissue whatsoever, making it
substantially less invasive than the most
commonly performed parallel for boys.x
Western culture has evidently come to a
point at which the taking of a sharp
viii
These laws do not literally have asterisks. In
the typical case, there is one statute banning
assault, or sexual assault, or invasive rites, or
child abuse, and then a second law saying that
no criminal violation shall result from ritual
(male) circumcision—even though it formally
fits the definition of assault/abuse in the first
law. For examples, see Geisheker.17
ix
Following the 1986 UN Convention on the
Rights of the Child.
x
See Davis.18 In contrast with the outright
prohibition of female genital cutting in Western
democracies, male genital cutting is not only
legally permitted, but is not even regulated. In
other words, in most parts of the world,
including in developed nations, any person, for
any reason, using any implement, in any
environment, with any degree of pain control
(or none), any amount of training (or none),
any assurance of a sanitary environment (or
none), and any level of medical knowledge (or
none), can attempt to perform genital surgery
on a newborn boy if it is claimed that the
procedure is a circumcision. It is only when
such lay attempts lead to emergency
hospitalisation of the infant because his life is
in danger that public concern becomes aroused.
See Geisheker17 for further discussion.
2
object to a little girl’s vulva is regarded as
being beyond the pale, no matter how
slight the intended incision, and no
matter how pious the motivation of the
parents. Since the same culture has so far
failed to reach an equivalent point in considering analogous incisions into (and
excisions from) the genitals of little boys,
one wonders why it has failed to do so,
and whether it should reasonably be
expected to move more sure-footedly in
that direction. The philosopher Anders
Sandberg has recently offered a useful
perspective on this matter:
… what is [likely] going on is [a] status
quo bias and [something about] the
social capital of religions. We are used to
[male] circumcision in Western culture,
so it is largely accepted. It is very similar
to how certain drugs are regarded as
criminal and worth fighting, yet other
drugs like alcohol are merely problems:
policy is set, [not] based on actual
harms, but based on a social acceptability scale and who has institutional
power. This all makes perfect sense
sociologically, but it is bad ethics.19
Getting practical
Be that as it may, sociological considerations
certainly do matter in the practical realm
of passing laws and making policy.
Accordingly, one argument against the
immediate prohibition of infant male circumcision is that Western cultures may
simply not yet be ready for so strict a legal
manoeuvre—especially in light of the
notorious ‘double standard’20 21 regarding
male versus female genital cutting that prevails in Anglophone societies. Indeed,
as Julian Savulescu,22 Matthew Johnson8
and Hanoch Ben Yami10 all point out, fully
fledged prohibitions instituted in advance
of cultural readiness can lead to troubling
side effects, such as a black market for the
banned practice, which in this case might
involve ‘back-alley’ circumcisions performed by incompetent individuals.
Accordingly, Savulescu advocates a policy
of harm reduction rather than prohibition;
Johnson suggests that religious groups
should be held accountable for any injuries
that do ensue from their ‘invasive rites’; and
Ben Yami outlines a series of gradual
reforms such as mandatory administration
of anaesthesia and the narrow illegalisation
of the metzitzah b’peh.xi Ben Yami argues
that these measures could reduce risk, pain
xi
Metzitzah b’peh is a form of circumcision
practiced by some Orthodox Jews in which the
ritual circumciser takes the baby’s penis into his
mouth to suck away the blood after the wound
has been inflicted, sometimes transmitting the
and suffering in the short-term while
contributing to a wider culture shift in the
long term.
CONCLUSION
With perspectives in this issue ranging from
Joseph Mazor’s7 articulate defence of infant
male circumcision as both morally and
legally permissiblexii to J Steven Svoboda’s14
contention that circumcision is an unambiguous affront to human rights, it is clear
that the debate on this issue is far from over.
Nevertheless, the overall balance of opinion
may be shifting toward one of general scepticism
concerning
circumcision—even
within religious communities. Increasingly,
individual Muslim and Jewish thinkers are
managing to persuade their fellow faith
practitioners that the involuntary ablation of
children’s foreskins is unnecessary for contemporary religious observance.xiii This type
of intra-religious influence can be traced at
least to the famous 19th century debates
within the German Jewish community concerning whether or not circumcision was to
be performed in the modern era.23 It continues today with the founding of such
groups as Jews Against Circumcision24 as
well as with the establishment of symbolic
alternatives to preputial amputation. One
such alternative is the non-violent, nonsexistxiv welcoming ceremony known as brit
shalomxv officiated by a growing number of
Jewish rabbis.25
As Dena Davis puts it in the title to her
essay,18 we are dealing with a fundamental
incompatibility between what she calls
‘ancient rites’ and ‘new laws.’ How this
incompatibility will be addressed, and
whether it can be dealt with in a way that
herpes virus. See the discussions by Ben Yami10
and Davis.18
xii
Mazor concedes, however, that circumcision
probably should not be performed in the
‘secular’ case when considering the child’s best
interests—one of which is an interest in
self-determination. He simply leaves the
ultimate decision up to the parents.
xiii
Of course, religious fundamentalists within
Islam and Judaism will not find these sorts of
arguments compelling, but they do not have—
and are not entitled to—a monopoly on
matters of theology, faith or ritual practice.
xiv
In
Judaism,
female
babies
are
unapologetically excluded from participation in
the sealing of the divine covenant; hence, the
practice is inherently sexist. Islam is more
‘egalitarian’ in permitting circumcision of girls
as well as boys.
xv
Brit shalom means ‘covenant of peace.’
Contrast with brit milah, the name for the
traditional Jewish genital cutting ceremony,
which
means
(loosely)
‘covenant
of
circumcision’ (milah means ‘to cut’). More
information on this alternative, peaceful brit
can be found by visiting the website at ref. 25
Earp BD. J Med Ethics Month 2013 Vol 00 No 00
Editorial
ensures not only the coherence and proper
functioning of religious communities but
also the well-being and basic rights of the
children being raised within their care—
only time will tell. This Special Issue on
circumcision marks an important contribution to the ongoing discussion. What is
needed now is productive and respectful
dialogue moving forward.
4
Competing interests None.
7
Provenance and peer review Commissioned;
internally peer reviewed.
To cite Earp BD. J Med Ethics Published Online First:
[ please include Day Month Year] doi:10.1136/
medethics-2013-101517
Received 5 April 2013
Accepted 11 April 2013
J Med Ethics 2013;00:1–3.
doi:10.1136/medethics-2013-101517
5
6
8
9
10
11
REFERENCES
1
2
3
American Academy of Pediatrics Task Force on
Circumcision. Male circumcision. Pediatrics
2012;130:e756–85.
American Academy of Pediatrics Task Force on
Circumcision 2012. The AAP Task Force on Neonatal
Circumcision: a call for respectful dialogue. J Med
Ethics Published Online First: 18 Mar 2013.
doi:10.1136/medethics-2013-101456
Svoboda JS, Van Howe RS. Out of step: fatal flaws in
the latest AAP policy report on neonatal circmcision.
J Med Ethics. Published Online First: 18 Mar 2013.
doi:10.1136/medethics-2013-101346
Earp BD. J Med Ethics Month 2013 Vol 00 No 00
12
13
14
15
Frisch M, Aigrain Y, Barauskas Y, et al. Cultural bias in
the AAP’s 2012 technical report and policy statement
on male circumcision. Pediatrics. Published Online First:
18 Mar 2013. doi:10.1542/peds.2012-2896
Earp BD. The AAP report on circumcision: bad science
+ bad ethics = bad medicine. Practical Ethics (blog),
30 Aug 2012. http://blog.practicalethics.ox.ac.uk/
2012/08/ the-aap-report-on-circumcision-bad-sciencebad-ethics-bad-medicine/ (accessed 31 Dec 2012).
Merkel R, Putzke H. After Cologne: male circumcision
and the law: parental right, religious liberty, or
criminal assault? J Med Ethics 2013, in press.
Mazor J. The child’s interests and the case for the
permissibility of male circumcision. J Med Ethics
2013, in press.
Johnson M. Religious circumcision, invasive rites,
neutrality and equality: bearing the burdens and
consequences of belief. J Med Ethics 2013, in press.
Hendel RS. That old time religion: the Bible preserves
hints of Stone Age rites that retained their holiness for
millennia. Biblical Archeology Review 2002;18:1–5.
Ben Yami H. Circumcision: what should be done?
J Med Ethics 2013, in press.
Van Howe RS. Infant circumcision: the last stand for
the dead dogma of parental (sovereignal) rights.
J Med Ethics 2013, in press.
Earp BD. Assessing a religious practice from
secular-ethical grounds: competing metaphysics in
the circumcision debate, and a note about discursive
respect. Proceedings of the 12th Annual International
Symposium on Law, Genital Autonomy, and
Children’s Rights. New York: Springer, forthcoming.
Earp BD. It’s OK to criticize religious practices. The
Philosophers’ Magazine 2013, in press.
Svoboda JS. Circumcision of male infants as a human
rights violation. J Med Ethics 2013, in press.
Darby RJL. The child’s right to an open future: is the
principle applicable to non-therapeutic circumcision?
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
J Med Ethics. Published Online First: 30 Jan 2013.
doi:10.1136/medethics-2012-101182
Earp BD, Darby RJL. Tradition vs. individual rights: the
current debate on circumcision. The Conversation, 2
Nov 2012. http://theconversation.com/tradition-vsindividual-rights-the-current-debate-oncircumcision-10199 (accessed 29 Mar 2013).
Geisheker JV. The completely unregulated practice of
male circumcision: human rights’ abuse enshrined in
law? New Male Studies 2013;2:18–45.
Davis D. Ancient rites and new laws: how should we
regulate religious circumcision of minors? J Med
Ethics 2013, in press.
Sandberg A. ‘It is interesting to consider a fictional
case...’ (29 Jun 2012). In response to: Earp BD. Can the
religious beliefs of parents justify the nonconsensual
cutting of their child’s genitals? Practical Ethics (blog),
28 Jun 2012. http://blog.practicalethics.ox.ac.uk/2012/
06/religion-is-no-excuse-for-mutilating-your-babys-penis/
(accessed 29 Mar 2013).
Darby R, Svoboda JS. A rose by any other name?
Rethinking the similarities and differences between
male and female genital cutting. Med Anthropol Q
2007;21:301–23.
Benatar D. The second sexism: discrimination against
men and boys. Oxford: John Wiley & Sons, 2012.
Savulescu J. Male circumcision and the enhancement
debate: harm reduction, not prohibition. J Med Ethics
2013, in press.
Heimbach-Steins M. Religious freedom and the
German circumcision debate. UEI Working Papers
2013; EUI Working Paper RSC AS 2013/18.
Jews Against Circumcision. http://www.
jewsagainstcircumcision.org/ (accessed 29 Mar
2013).
Beyond the bris: questioning Jewish circumcision.
http://www.beyondthebris.com/ (accessed 29 Mar
2013).
3